Tuesday, March 12, 2024

A Critique of Brute Facts as Explanation


Maybe there really isn't a need for an absolutely simple being, as deduced from stage one of the Argument from Composition. Why can't it be what is called a brute fact that accounts for composite beings? This article will have me briefly discuss my thoughts on such an objection. I won't be repeating the Argument from Composition here, so it's recommended that one takes a look at the original article.

Also, while my comments here are specifically targeted towards the use of brute facts as an objection towards the Argument from Composition, the same could be said for the use of brute facts as an objection to anything at all.

In the context of the Argument from Composition, one might object that it's merely a brute fact that composite beings exist and that their parts are composed in this specific manner, needing no explanation.

1 Brute Facts

Brute facts are facts that don't have any explanations, but just are. For example, some atheists may claim that the existence of the universe is a brute fact, requiring no further explanation. Or some theistic personalists may claim that the existence of God and His attributes, on their model, are just brute facts.

2 Non-explanations

One issue with using such an approach to argue for or against a position is that to say that something is a brute fact to explain a fact is, by definition, no explanation at all. In the end, the one positing something as a brute fact in order to account for it has just admitted that they have not given any explanation or account of the fact in question.

So, they should accept the original account of the fact in question, in this case, the absolutely simple being, until they provide an alternative explanation or refute the arguments that the advocate of the Argument from Composition has put forward.

If not, it seems to me to be simply question begging to not engage with the arguments while asserting that your position is simply true.

3 Good Hypothesis?

Further, as alluded to above, the existence of brute facts in one's hypothesis affects its viability, as compared to opposing hypotheses.

A hypothesis is just a proposed explanation for a phenomenon. In more colloquial, albeit inaccurate, terms, it could be said to be a theory, of sorts, to account for a certain set of facts.

While the philosophy of science is not something that I've read much into, I am aware that when assessing the validity and plausibility of a hypothesis, simplicity and ad hocness are important factors.

3.1 Simplicity

A hypothesis is simpler when it proposes fewer entities and explanatory mechanisms to account for more facts.

For example, the hypothesis that there were nine unobserved planets orbiting somewhere out in space to explain the slightly skewed orbit of an observed planet would be less simple than the hypothesis that there were just one planet orbiting somewhere. Of course, this is given that both the former and latter hypotheses adequately account for the data.

3.2 Ad Hocness

A hypothesis is less ad hoc when it proposes less random or unnecessary entities and explanatory mechanisms, staying within the given data as far as it can.

For example, when trying to explain a murder. It would be ad hoc to say that there was a fairy in the room when the murder was committed, as this goes beyond the evidence and observations, and is random, as well as unnecessary.

3.3 Bruteness

According to the above criteria, positing unjustified brute facts as part of one's hypothesis would be ad hoc and make the hypothesis less simple.

Consider that I bake a cake and leave it out to cool, and when I return the cake is gone, while only an empty tray remains. Let us now consider two hypotheses. First, that the cake was eaten by my brother, who has done this many times in the past. Second, that it is a brute fact that the cake would disappear on that day, at that time, and that the cake that would disappear would be the one that I specifically baked.

The second hypothesis is far less simple than the first. At first, one may think that it is simpler because the first hypothesis posits my brother while the second does not.

However, upon further reflection, we realise that the first hypothesis posits my brother, who we already know is likely to do such a thing, and that cakes usually don't disappear randomly. The first hypothesis very nicely accounts for all of our background information while only positing one entity and explanatory mechanism, my brother, and maybe his hunger.

But the second hypothesis is far less simple and more ad hoc since it assumes that out of all possible times, and completely contrary to all past experience, my specific cake would disappear at that specific time on that specific day. The explanatory mechanism here is extremely ad hoc and violates all of our background knowledge about cakes and causation and what not. And its simplicity also takes a huge hit from this as we're positing a lot more that goes beyond the data[that at this specific time, on this specific day, my specific cake would disappear]: many more things would have to align perfectly for this hypothesis.

So, we should favour the first hypothesis as it is more simple and less ad hoc, until extra evidence and argument is given for the second hypothesis or arguments for the first are refuted.

3.4 Science

It would also be profitable to note that the explanatory principles that I bring up above are commonly used in not only the philosophy of science but science itself, and without them scientists would have a lot of trouble coming to any substantive conclusions based on their experiments.

For example, take our discovery that the local universe started to exist approximately 26.7 billion years ago. In order to come to such a conclusion, we not only had to gather data, such as detecting the cosmic microwave background radiation, or to ascertain that the universe really was expanding, but also had to come up with hypotheses that could explain this data.

Now, using explanatory principles like how close a hypothesis stays to the data and having it be less ad hoc, we managed to find that the best explanation of this data is that the universe began to exist 26.7 billion years ago.

Using these explanatory principles, we could also rule out more ad hoc and less simple hypotheses like that the speed of light changed and the universe was really 6000 years old, or that all these observations were just brute facts that had no explanation. If scientists gave countenance to the latter, then science as we know it would end.

4 Conclusion

In conclusion, positing brute facts as an explanation for a given phenomena, especially without sufficient justification, serves as a non-explanation and can be shown to have, in light of certain inductive and explanatory principles used in science, to be rejected in favour of other hypotheses that do serve as a better explanation. While this does not necessarily ascertain the truth or falsity of a hypothesis, it is the best way that we can go about handling data that we have.

No comments:

Post a Comment